No kidding. You can stop back-peddling. The problem claim is not that measure theory isn't relevant, it is your claim that:
This is patently false, absurd nonsense. You have confused an application of measure theory, or a use of measure theory, with what you claim measure theory to be, an "essentially" so.
You are wrong. Until you can show me how cannot have a notion of measure without operator theory or how every measure that can be constructed must necessarily be (at least trivially) an example of commutative operator theory (and then explain, while you are back-peddling anyway, how I get to to use measure theory anyway for non-commutative spaces and algebras and in fact how you have defined measure theory in a way that is incredibly restrictive and discounts its central uses in many fundamental formulations of QM), then you can go on about "measure theory" all you want. It doesn't appear you know enough about operator algebras, measure theory, or quantum theory to be relevant here.
I clearly know more of the mathematics involved than you. I thought you had a bit more background, but that is clearly not the case.
I might suggest reading a *good* operator theory book, like Kadison+Ringrose volume I. Rudin's book on Functional Analysis also does a good job with the basics (like a proof of the spectral theorem for normal operators and a treatment of closed unbounded operators).
When you are done back-peddling there, and have finished claiming on the one hand that Hilbert spaces aren't necessarily function spaces because they need not be L2 (never said they did; a function space is a generalization of a vector space, and a vector space is trivially a function space, so all Hilbert and Banach and even normed (linear) spaces are function spaces, even if only trivially so), while on the other hand claiming that your statements regarding operator algebras are relevant here even when all we need for Bell tests and the like is complex matrices (which I'll admit now, to spare you the trouble of stating this obvious fact later, that as operators are generalizations of entities such as matrices, complex matrices are trivially "operators" and the matrix algebra of complex matrices is necessarily, albeit trivially, a noncommutative operator algebra), then perhaps we can make progress.
You are wrong about vector spaces all being function spaces. Not even close. But that is irrelevant to the main discussion.
Good. Algebras of matrices are (finite dimensional) operator algebras. And that is NOT trivial since, as you even point out, the crucial aspects like violation of Bell's inequalities occur at this level.
Stop back-peddling. I never claimed that linear functionals or duals or anything related to Banach, Hilbert, pre-Hilbert, or normed spaces of any sort weren't "measures" or that they couldn't be considered meausres.
It's the ridiculous claim
You were clearly not understanding my point thought. See my last post.
that I have a problem with. It is not essentially this at all. It is much more general, hence it's power. Operators require much more structure than measures.
[/QUOTE]
Yes, I see where your confusion arises.
Let's go over some basics.
A Banach space is a vector space with a norm making it into a complete metric space. If you need definitions, I can provide them.
A Hilbert space is a vector space with a positive definite inner product that is a Banach space under the induced norm. Again, if you need definitions, I can give them.
A Banach algebra is a Banach space with an associative multiplication (and usually an identity) that distributes over addition and commutes with scalar multiplication. In addition, we assume the morm is submultiplicative.
A C* algebra is a Banach algebra with an involution x->x* such that the norm of xx* is the same as the square of the norm of x. For convenience, I assume all C* algebras are complex vector spaces.
Are we good here? Or do you need me to give more detail?
Examples of C* algebras:
1. The collection of bounded operators on a Hilbert space (do I need to define this?). If H is the Hilbert space, this C* algebra is denoted by B(H) and the * operation is the adjoint map. This algebra is non-commutative if H has dimension more than 1.
2. If X is a compact Hausdorff space, the set of continuous complex valued functions C(X) is a C* algebra with usual multiplication and complex conjugation as the * operation. This is a commutative C* algebra. One crucial fact is that ALL commutative C* algebras are isomorphic to one like this.
3. If H is a Hilbert space, the collection of compact operators (do I need to define these for you?) is, as a subspace of B(H), a C* subalgebra. For finite dimensional H, this is identical to B(H), but they differ a lot in the infinite dimensional setting.
4. The collection of all bounded sequences of complex numbers is a commutative C* algebra with appropriate operations. This is another commutative C* algebra.
Now, in any C* algebra, we can define an element to be self-adjoint if x*=x and normal if x*x=xx*. Obviously every element of a commutative C* algebra is normal.
More subtly, we can define an element to be positive if it is of the form x*x. It turns out that elements of this form are closed under addition and multiplication by positive real numbers (they form a cone). Every element can then be written as a linear combination of positive elements with 4 terms.
Again, not the problem. I never disagreed that measure theory was relevant here. And you are back-peddling again. We've gone from
Ultimately, the point is that measure theory is, essentially, commutative operator theory.
to
we can identify the collection of measures in that context with the dual of the space of continuous functions
Which is the essence of the identification.
On the contrary, you are now trying to talk about how measure theory is used in a particular context. That's great. It's not what you said. When you want to address the glaringly, obviously incorrect statements you initially made and stop back-peddling, great.
As relevant to discussions of QM, measure theory is essentially commutative operator theory. Yes, you can define measures in more generality, but the most relevant cases are those where the collection of measures is the dual of the space of continuous functions. Operator theorists tend to see measure theory as the commutative version of their topic. Get off your high horse and maybe learn a different perspective.
Von Neuman developed Hilbert space and his algebras to do this. QM isn't based on it. Also, the inequality in question is not based on quatum mechanics.
I didn't say it was. It is based on the fact that operators on a Hilbert space form a non-commutative C* algebra. Bell's inequality is what is found in the commutative setting with integration against a measure.
A central point behind Bell's theorem is that the inequality doesn't need QM at all. It can work for any theory as it need deal only with the relative frequencies of experimental outcomes and corresponding experimental (device) settings.
It works for any probability space.
Thus, QM is only relevant when one seeks non-trivial ways to violate the inequality, and a central point for Bell and others afterwards (and a central misunderstanding) is that even were QM to be replaced, since the inequalities don't require the theory, whatever replaced QM would still have to deal with the inequality violations.
Agreed. And *why* does QM violate these inequalities? Because of the non-commutativity of the operators and the way they operate on the states.
So, for the commutative setting (where the elements of the C* algebra are continuous functions on some compact Hausdorff space), a 'state' is integration with respect to a probability measure. So, for example, if 0<=|f|,|g|,|h|,|k|<=1, then (using <f,u> for the integral of f with respect to u).
<fh+fk+gh-gk, u> <= 2
In the non-commutative setting, the elements of the C* algebra are operators and the 'states' are the functionals of the form A--><Ax,x> with x a ray. The corresponding inequality for *operators* 0<= A,B,C,D <= I
<(AC+AD+BC-BD)x,x> <= 2
Fails.
Most of the operators involved are 'closed operators' when defined on those dense subspaces
No, they aren't. How do I know? Because I am talking about unbounded opeartors specifically and how they they can't be treated in the ways they often are not only in the textbooks but also too often in the physics literature. I am not talking about how operators can or can't be defined generally, but about (in this case) problems related to the treatment operators and the spaces they act on in term of a disregard for rigor.
Yes, I am also talking about unbounded operators. They are defined on dense subsets of the Hilbert spaces, but have the crucial property that their graph is closed (which is why they are called closed operators). In particular, differential operators have this property.
And, for closed operators, we can get a good version of the spectral theorem assuming the 'right' notion of self-adjointness (some caution is required, I will admit).
Again, a decent source for this development is Rudin's book on Functional Analysis.
Since your approach to rigor lacks even this level of care, I am not really very concerned with what you want to regurgitate about operators when you can't seem to decide whether you know basic measure theory.
Again, no need to insult. I guarantee I know more measure theory than you. This type of thing was my research specialty.
If your knowledge of measure theory and operator algebras is this abysmal, then you are in luck: we don't need any of this for the relevant systems in QM that violate Bell's inequality. And better still, since you don't understand the Bell's theorem either, you don't even need QM to understand the inequality!
Yes, I understand the definitions you are using. I am saying that they only give a very small part of the picture. By the way, it isn't non-commutative operators--it is non-commutative operator *algebras*. And, again, no need for insults when your own understanding is not at the level I was expecting.
1) EPR implicitly show that locality implies (and requires) a theory to have some sort of structure or nature X
2) Bell shows explicitly, but building on EPR (hence the name of his 1964 paper) that whatever X is, it can be tested empirically.
3) QM's predictions violate X
This is based on the assumption that you use measure theory for the relevant correlations. But that is wrong in the context of QM, where the correlations are computed not with integration of a function against some measure, but via an inner product of an operator applied to a state and that state.
And yes, Bell is correct. No measure on a measure space can reproduce the results of states on operators.
2) & 3) have both turned out to be true (we knew 3) was true before Bell in one sense, as Bell didn't do much in the way of theoretical work on QM to get a violation of his inequality).
Hence, QM is nonlocal, because there is no way to explain the violations of the inequality that hold indepdently of any theory concerning measurement outcomes that is required for locality but is violated by experiment (and, also, by QM, but as importantly by any would-be replacement of QM).
That is only true if you assume the underlying states are described via a probability space. And that is precisely what fails in QM.