It doesn't matter. A sorites "argument" is an instance of the paradox.I don't think he is talking about the paradox.
Welcome to Religious Forums, a friendly forum to discuss all religions in a friendly surrounding.
Your voice is missing! You will need to register to get access to the following site features:We hope to see you as a part of our community soon!
It doesn't matter. A sorites "argument" is an instance of the paradox.I don't think he is talking about the paradox.
I think he is referring to the polysyllogismIt doesn't matter. A sorites "argument" is an instance of the paradox.
Which would by definition require a non-Aristotelian many-valued logic.I think he is referring to the polysyllogism
I don't need to. I saw "sorites" as defined in the text cited (and basically plagiarized). Also, the uses you refer to are examples of the sorites paradox.See sorites as used here:
Which would by definition require a non-Aristotelian many-valued logic.
I don't need to. I saw "sorites" as defined in the text cited (and basically plagiarized). Also, the uses you refer to are examples of the sorites paradox.
Sorites arguments of the paradoxical form are to be distinguished from multi-premise syllogisms (polysyllogisms) which are sometimes also referred to as sorites arguments.
1) The relationship you describe between language and logic (e.g., the copula or any similarly stative verb or verbal construction and predicates in Aristotelian/classical logic)
2) The nature of the Sorites paradox or sorites arguments (the two are identical; see your own text A Concise Introduction to Logic (11th Ed.) here: "A sorites is a chain of categorical syllogisms in which the intermediate conclusions have been left out. The name is derived from the Greek word soros, meaning “heap,” and is pronounced “sōrītëz,” with the accent on the second syllable. The plural form is also “sorites.”; the relevant example is that one might find in a textbook on many-valued and/or fuzzy logics- an argument that requires a reasoning chain in which the truth values of certain propositions are not binary but rather depend upon vague quantifications or degrees).
4) All your claims about Aristotle
5) The nature of syllogistic arguments
6) The nature of the word "philosopher" and all other references to any terms found in Aristotle or Greek literature more generally.
7) Elementary linguistic terms such as "noun phrase" and their relationship to logic.
7) QUANTIFICATION
You've ripped off Hurley's text from the Concise Introduction series, but don't understand it. The predicate is a VERB (and can be a copula). The predicate relates the subject to what you (following Hurley) call the "predicate term" and what most of us familiar with logic would call an "argument", "variable", etc., or just not refer to at all but rather rely on the multiplicity of the predicate itself and a subsequent appropriate designation (e.g., a "two-place" predicate will necessarily have two "terms" that are related to the "subject" by the predicate). The "middle term" Hurley refers to is simply the component shared by the (by definition) two-premise form of a syllogism. One cannot, from two premises, infer the validity of anything from these two unless they relate in some way, namely in that they refer to the same "object", concept, etc., or properties of one of these ("All crows are black" & X is not black " are related by the property "BLACK" as applied to crows, and therefore allow us to infer that X is not a crow).
That's because it does. It's a central reason for many-valued logics, all of which are non-Aristotelian
The etymology is simply the use of the Greek word in relation to a (sand) heap. If one removes a grain of sand from a sand heap, it is still a heap of sand. But remove enough grains, and you will eventually be left with a single grain. There is no point at which a heap goes from being a heap to not a heap given a single removal of a grain of sand, yet Aristotelian logic demands this.
I'm aware. I've not only written about this but served as a consult for others here. The problem is that you don't seem to be familiar with these sources except to the extent you don't understand them. That's why, when I ask for citations, I don't mean sources, but literally citing specific parts of sources (particularly Aristotle) that would support the things you state.
A paradox is a type of argument pattern. A "sorites argument" is an argument that is strictly invalid in Aristotelian logic but problematically so.
.
You regurgitated them from Hurley, and badly.
Wrong. Our disagreement is far more fundamental. I don't think you have any knowledge of logic or Aristotle beyond the kind demonstrated by your various inaccurate regurgitations of a book from the Concise Introduction series on modern Logic. Thus you speak about Aristotelian logic but have shown to be incapable of referring to Aristotle. You speak of propositions but fail even to deal with them as Aristotle does, let alone recognize the fundamental problems with Aristotelian "proposition" (see e.g., his discussion of ναυμαχία and its relation to modern possible world semantics and modal logic).I think our disagreement is and it resolves around what a proposition is.
Who cares? For someone so keen on leaping upon the falsely seeming etymological argument, you are sure caught up with irrelevant terminology here. Your own source doesn't use the term paradox, but describes exactly the same thing.I will prove to you later that multiple sources use the term SORITES without mentioning any paradox.
No, you didn't. You just ripped him off. I own Hurley's book (I have taught this subject for years). I know how much you relied on the presentation in this source.I never attempted to cite any author Hurley
I've never met any philosophers or mathematicians who equated sentences with propositions. This is so obviously wrong as to be a priori ludicrous (think of the imperative mood).It seems there is a generation of philosophers in a philosophy department (and all math professors I see) that teach a proposition is A SENTENCE.
They can't, except ideally and therefore formally (mathematically), abstracted away from any meaning. See e.g., Grayling's (An Introduction to Philosophical Logic) example of "Der Schnee ist weiß" and "The snow is white").Propositions can express the same idea using different words literally.
And a sentence is?More than one PhD qualified professor EXPRESSED the same idea: a proposition is NOT physical.
Not according to Aristotle. This would entail fatalism (as he states in detail), and therefore is not "truth-bearing" (is not a proposition).The proposition "there will be a sea battle in the reed sea" is a proposition and has a truth value that is either true or false.
Not according to Aristotle, and there is nothing about major and minor premises in a syllogism that is an "art" rather than something far more exact and precise than any of the sciences.Logic that I discussed above is not a science in this regard but an art.
Which is about as meaningful as discussing the musical side of logic, or the astrological side of logic.What I am discussing is the art side of logic.
Logic isn't normal. It isn't even intuitive. It was developed precious few times even in the non-formal way Aristotle did. Your misuses of terms from Hurley demonstrate this doubly, as 1) they are misuses and 2) the are not terms or concepts found in normal communication. Some 50 years of research in the cognitive sciences and elsewhere have shown that people do not, in general, think logically without training (even such basic logical inferences as "If A, then B THEN if not B, then not A" prove too challenging, as does the non-equivalence of "If A, then B" and "If B, then A").Normal communication is not what I expressed you are to use categorical form.
Coming from someone who uses terms like "noun phrase", "copula", "minor premise", "syllogism", etc., in a post explicitly related to a development by a Greek over 2 millennia ago, this particular statement is pretty comical.If you want to use modern language then do so but you ought not do so if you express an argument and want the argument evaluated.
Wrong. Our disagreement is far more fundamental. I don't think you have any knowledge of logic or Aristotle beyond the kind demonstrated by your various inaccurate regurgitations of a book from the Concise Introduction series on modern Logic. Thus you speak about Aristotelian logic but have shown to be incapable of referring to Aristotle. You speak of propositions but fail even to deal with them as Aristotle does, let alone recognize the fundamental problems with Aristotelian "proposition" (see e.g., his discussion of ναυμαχία and its relation to modern possible world semantics and modal logic).
Who cares? For someone so keen on leaping upon the falsely seeming etymological argument, you are sure caught up with irrelevant terminology here. Your own source doesn't use the term paradox, but describes exactly the same thing.
No, you didn't. You just ripped him off. I own Hurley's book (I have taught this subject for years). I know how much you relied on the presentation in this source.
I've never met any philosophers or mathematicians who equated sentences with propositions. This is so obviously wrong as to be a priori ludicrous (think of the imperative mood).
They can't, except ideally and therefore formally (mathematically), abstracted away from any meaning. See e.g., Grayling's (An Introduction to Philosophical Logic) example of "Der Schnee ist weiß" and "The snow is white").
And a sentence is?
Not according to Aristotle. This would entail fatalism (as he states in detail), and therefore is not "truth-bearing" (is not a proposition).
Not according to Aristotle, and there is nothing about major and minor premises in a syllogism that is an "art" rather than something far more exact and precise than any of the sciences.
Which is about as meaningful as discussing the musical side of logic, or the astrological side of logic.
Logic isn't normal. It isn't even intuitive. It was developed precious few times even in the non-formal way Aristotle did. Your misuses of terms from Hurley demonstrate this doubly, as 1) they are misuses and 2) the are not terms or concepts found in normal communication. Some 50 years of research in the cognitive sciences and elsewhere have shown that people do not, in general, think logically without training (even such basic logical inferences as "If A, then B THEN if not B, then not A" prove too challenging, as does the non-equivalence of "If A, then B" and "If B, then A").
Coming from someone who uses terms like "noun phrase", "copula", "minor premise", "syllogism", etc., in a post explicitly related to a development by a Greek over 2 millennia ago, this particular statement is pretty comical.
Perhaps it is because you duplicate exactly his terminology which, to one familiar with texts on logic more generally, is idiomatic.You are making a lot of assumptions above. Again I did not rip off Hurley or any other author who express the same concepts as I do. Why you insist on saying or expressing a read Hurley and ran away with it in the wrong direction is quite comical to me.
You don't cite catholic sources (and you can't here; even catholic Priests or friars can't define "Cathologic" logic and certainly can't define anything as Catholic Aristotelian logic, as Aristotle predates the Catholic church).I will put this in proper perspective below and CITE the context you seem to misrepresent. I want to be clear that what I have stated has been taught for quite some time in Catholic education as some of my sources will show.
Correct. Now, what you have to demonstrate is that any of your ad hoc citations shows differently. You don't. You quote a bunch of random sources which one could easily discover via google, but don't demonstrate how these indicate a difference between a sorites "argument" and the paradox.I also want to make clear YOUR claim was a Sorites cannot be separated from a paradox.
FINALLY! A citation (if indirect) from Aristotle! Alas, it simply gives evidence against your use of sorites and your understanding of Aristotelian logic, for it is mere evidence that the sorites paradox (or "argument" or whatever you wish) was foreign to Aristotle, as indeed it was (at least insofar as our sources tell).In Aristotle epicheireme means an attempt at demonstration as opposed to a demonstration properly so called.
{1} The enthymeme is commonly reckoned among the more or less disguised forms of the syllogism, as though it consisted
merely in leaving one of the premises to be understood, not expressed. This is too secondary a circumstance to justify
giving the enthymeme a place of its own among the forms of syllogism. As a matter of fact Aristotle understood by
enthymeme a syllogism the conclusion of which is only more or less. probable.
Something COMPLETELY absent from your posts, and therefore irrelevant to any of your claims about them. You can't claim to have addressed anything related to polysyllogisms when you didn't address these, and you haven't related these to the sorites paradox, making the above another pointless claim.The Sorites is an abridged Polysyllogism
Sister Miriam Joseph. (1937)
My sister attended CUA. My brother attended CUA and two other more "hardcore" catholic universities. Other than I, my whole family is catholic. I've read Catholic writings from the pre-Scholastics past the early Modern era. I've also read Aristotle and the Patristics. As "Aristotelian" logic doesn't accord with your misrepresentation of Hurley, neither does the Catholic church'sI was TAUGHT it. The Catholic church has tried to keep Aristotelian logic
It predated Aquinas by many centuries.This is likely do to Saint Thomas Aquinas and many others who followed in Aquinas' foot steps. Note that all of the catholic sources seem to express the SAME IDEAS and that is how it was taught. Catholic sources that teach logic is quite different from non-Catholic sources.
Perhaps it is because you duplicate exactly his terminology which, to one familiar with texts on logic more generally, is idiomatic.
You don't cite catholic sources (and you can't here; even catholic Priests or friars can't define "Cathologic" logic and certainly can't define anything as Catholic Aristotelian logic, as Aristotle predates the Catholic church).
Correct. Now, what you have to demonstrate is that any of your ad hoc citations shows differently. You don't. You quote a bunch of random sources which one could easily discover via google, but don't demonstrate how these indicate a difference between a sorites "argument" and the paradox.
FINALLY! A citation (if indirect) from Aristotle! Alas, it simply gives evidence against your use of sorites and your understanding of Aristotelian logic, for it is mere evidence that the sorites paradox (or "argument" or whatever you wish) was foreign to Aristotle, as indeed it was (at least insofar as our sources tell).
Something COMPLETELY absent from your posts, and therefore irrelevant to any of your claims about them. You can't claim to have addressed anything related to polysyllogisms when you didn't address these, and you haven't related these to the sorites paradox, making the above another pointless claim.
My sister attended CUA. My brother attended CUA and two other more "hardcore" catholic universities. Other than I, my whole family is catholic. I've read Catholic writings from the pre-Scholastics past the early Modern era. I've also read Aristotle and the Patristics. As "Aristotelian" logic doesn't accord with your misrepresentation of Hurley, neither does the Catholic church's
It predated Aquinas by many centuries.
You realize that the entire point of the paradox (or a central point) is the formulation of syllogisms which result in paradoxes, right? You seem rather obsessed with distinguishing the sorites paradox with a sorites argument when in reality they are equivalent: a series of statements following what should be a series of truth-preserving inferences but can yield a paradoxical conclusion because of the nature of sorties arguments.I would like to point out I have shown without question that the sorties is a type of syllogism. You are obsessed with the sorties paradox
You quoted Hurley's description, and plagiarized Hurley for your original posts.I quoted Hurley directly and you did not show me how Hurley's own example is a PARADOX.
20 years in logic and you have to rely on out of print books and those available for free online to cover for ripping off of Hurley? And after explicit claims about what Aristotle said, you can't even point to places in a translation where he does.Again I point out that I have over 20 years in logic.
The point of the Brief Introduction series is to provide an elementary familiarity for those who have no background knowledge of the topic as simply as possible. So these texts usually don't conform to typical texts intended to actually be used to teach the topic or be used as a textbook. As such they use different strategies, terms, etc., than one finds in more typical sources used to learn these topics. I've taught and tutored the philosophy of logic, symbolic logic, mathematical logic, set theory, and related topics long enough to know standard presentations. Your presentation wasn't just non-standard, but includes verbatim quotes and nearly verbatim quotes from the non-standard text you then cited.I have had qualified PhD instructors but you make up what you like about me and say I plagiarized Hurley. I don't get it.
RECENT? One was practically published in the 19th century, another from the 30s, and none were recent.I pointed out that the recent sources
That's easy. Yours. One of your sources uses the term "enthymemes". Another favors epicheireme (although lists enthymeme), and the third uses neither.Show me a Catholic source that uses DIFFERENT terminology please.
Tarski not only taught at a major Catholic college but received an honorary degree from there. Bolzano wasn't just Catholic and a logician who embraced mathematics but was a mathematician. Professor of Logic Peter Geach was awarded the papal cross. A center of development of mathematical logic, the Warsaw Logical school, contained no few devout Catholics. And the "mathematical bandwagon" only goes back to Frege.I stated to you that the Catholic Church tried to stay true to the classical system and not jump on the modern mathematical bandwagon.
No, they don't. Few do. And most students majoring in mathematics have a woefully inadequate knowledge of mathematical logic. This is partly because formal logic remains philosophical despite its mathematical nature, partly because of the use of set theory as a common language for logicians and mathematicians that make it unnecessary for logicians or mathematicians to study mathematical logic, and partly because non-mathematical logic is already mathematical enough even as covered in philosophy of logic. Hence its designation as a formal system or language.I would say now most student in logic will learn mathematical logic. Would you agree?
So is writing. Logic, mathematical or no, relies on formally defined mathematical rules that license or justify the inference of premises, statements, etc., from others based on formal frameworks. It is impossible to determine the validity of an argument using logic without a mathematical framework of axioms, schemata, or similar set of "rules" sanctioning inferences that are truth-preserving.Mathematical logic is symbol manipulation.
Aristotelian logic IS classical logic.It does not look for deceptive techniques which classical logic does.
Aristotelian logic is also called classical logic. Both terms are used to distinguish the logical tradition Aristotle founded from e.g., modal logic, tense logic, quantum logic, and other logics not equivalent with Aristotelian logic. Mathematical logic/symbolic logic IS equivalent, and IS called Aristotelian logic.[/QUOTE]I think you are taking Aristotle so literally you have missed the additional information added to classical logic.
I can read ancient Greek. The terms are not a problem. The fact that you back your claim about "Catholic logic" or "Catholic logicians" by citing a "recent" text written a over a century ago, a text that wasn't even a logic text but more general, and an out-of-print book that just so happens to have the pages you quoted from online is the problem.You seem unfamiliar with the terms I quoted.
Finally. The paradox is how the logical chain can involve only valid statements and thus fulfill Hurley's criterion ("The rule in evaluating a sorites is based on the idea that a chain is only as strong as its weakest link. If any of the component syllogisms in a sorites is invalid, the entire sorites is invalid"), yet still be invalid. The paradox isn't that all sorites arguments are paradoxical, but that sorites lead to paradoxes:Show me the Paradox specifically using the example Hurley gave and I quoted earlier.
Not frequently, at least not for those of us who don't go looking for century-old texts to quote-mine from:The terms enthymemes, sorites are found in typical logic texts and works.
Then you didn't really look very hard. Kennedy defines it as follows:Epicheirema is not a typical logic term and I found only catholic source use that term as well as Polly syllogism
Out of curiosity, what are the "standard" Catholic works? Century old obscure texts you found online aren't standard, but obscure. "Standard" texts aren't out-of-print, for example.and other terms not found standard non catholic works.
I'm not, actually. The terms aren't used in all of your sources, they aren't used quite the same if they are shared, and therefore fulfill your request.You are under the thinking enthymemes and epicheirema are identical and its your mistake.
I find it laughable that you claim to have the experience you do but rely on obscure texts available on line and one Concise Introduction series book on logic which you plagiarize from. I have lots of books with both those words (the LSJ, all the LOEB volumes with Aristotle's works, Cicero's De Inventione, several logic texts and even more on argumentation and rhetoric or the history of these, etc.). True, some are in other language like German, but not all (e.g., "a specific type of complex argument...the epicheirema, also called the five-part argument" in Henkemans, A. F. S. (2001). Argumentation Structures. Crucial Concepts in Aargumentation Theory (pp. 101-134). Amsterdam University Press.William t. parry and Edward Hacker also have a text called Aritotelian Logic which you will find uses the same terminology as the other sources I mentioned and you think are laughable.
I don't dislike them. It's not the texts, it's why you relied on them.The fact you dislike some sources is besides the point.
So does logic. So does probability, arithmetic, geometry, etc., but unlike these and other areas which were once solely in the domain of philosophy, set theory remains deeply ingrained in philosophy and intricately and inexorably bound with logic. Mathematical logic was invented by a philosopher (Frege) and then developed by philosophers (Russell, Whitehead, Lewis, Łukasiewicz, Tarski, Kripke, etc.) and continues to be developed, taught, and contributed to by philosophers (e.g., my intro to mathematical logic professor). The founder of the Journal of Symbolic Logic and a founder of computability theory (also intricately tied to logic) was not only a philosopher but deeply religiousSet theory directly belongs to math.
None of them had many-valued logic either. Some texts by philosophers combine set theory and logic, and I have several textbooks I've taught with that are definitely mathematical but contain entire chapters on logic. You should probably read Logic And Theism.None of the logic texts --written by PHILOSOPHERS -- I mentioned including HURLEY, COPI and COHEN, etc have set theory anywhere in the text.
Not at all. It is clearly a subject of mathematics (as is logic), and much of mathematics are subjects of philosophy.Are you specifically saying SET TEHORY is not a component of MATH?
Set theory didn't exist until the 19th century. It was invented by Cantor. Also, the distinction between and philosophy is recent.Philosophers prior to the 19th century had no need for set theory and was not taught in PHILOSOPHY.
There wasn't any serious distinction, partly because mathematicians were all philosophers and partly because of colloquial vs. scholarly senses of the term.Math and logic have not been connected in a serious way until then.
Not really (at least no more than those learning logic are learning set theory).If students are learning SET THEORY then they are for sure learning MATHEMATICAL LOGIC.
Wrong. Not only does it appear in many a logic text including those that aren't mathematical, but in philosophy of logic texts.Set theory is MATH and only MATH.
Or I know something about the history and practice of both subjects. Aristotle connected logic with geometry and both were forms of mathematics (also a Greek word).You cannot have set theory without math. You seemed to think the other way around.
Predicate logic began with Aristotle.Predicate logic hides the middle term from view.
No, you can't. You can't even evaluate most derivations/arguments from classical propositional logic if you with such limitations. For example, "either it is raining or it isn't" must be true but is one proposition and "it is raining and not raining" is false but is again one proposition.Once I know the middle term I can go from classical to predicate logic and vice versa.
You have misunderstood what I stated. I stated the terms such as epicheirema, and Material Logic were recent in relation to the logic time line: classical logic, medieval logic, modern logic (symbolic logic which includes Predicate logic) and the most recent MATHEMATICAL LOGIC.The fact that you back your claim about "Catholic logic" or "Catholic logicians" by citing a "recent" text written a over a century ago, a text that wasn't even a logic text but more general, and an out-of-print book that just so happens to have the pages you quoted from online is the problem.
You did not address what I asked but gave YOUR example. I specifically stated use Hurley's example. I guess you saw that ALL SORITES do not necessarily lead to paradoxes! Let me fix part of your quote for you: "The paradox isn't that all sorites arguments are paradoxical, but that [SOME] sorites [CAN] lead to paradoxes . . . "Finally. The paradox is how the logical chain can involve only valid statements and thus fulfill Hurley's criterion ("The rule in evaluating a sorites is based on the idea that a chain is only as strong as its weakest link. If any of the component syllogisms in a sorites is invalid, the entire sorites is invalid"), yet still be invalid. The paradox isn't that all sorites arguments are paradoxical, but that sorites lead to paradoxes:
Wrong thread.I think therefore ...I am
I like it simple
Propositional logic was developed by "mathematicians" (in so far as you wish to differentiate the philosophers from Leibniz onward, who founded symbolic logic before Boole was born, and philosophers). Predicate logic wasn't developed until after Boole was dead. As for Medieval logic, one of the primary methods used to advance it was splitting apart Aristotelian logic into two:You have misunderstood what I stated. I stated the terms such as epicheirema, and Material Logic were recent in relation to the logic time line: classical logic, medieval logic, modern logic (symbolic logic which includes Predicate logic) and the most recent MATHEMATICAL LOGIC.
Islamic scholars developed algebra. The scholastics didn't do that much to expand upon Aristotle (and what they did do can't exactly be seen as an expansion of Aristotle as they weren't presented with a consistent, singular Aristotelian logic thanks to the lack of access to Aristotle's texts), and in fact it was Galileo's challenging of Aristotle more than Catholicism that got him in trouble. Once post-scholastic philosophy and therefore mathematics really got going, we find (voila!) an entire system of mathematical logic present in the 1600s thanks to Leibniz. On p. 591 of my edition of Russell's A History of Western Philosophy, we find that Leibniz "did work on mathematical logic which would have been enormously important if he had published it; he would, in that case, have been the founder of mathematical logic, which would have become known a century and a half sooner than it did in fact."Like I said earlier, many logic concepts were expanded from the original Aristotle texts namely from Islamic scholars and Catholic scholars in the medieval time period.
Boole was also a philosopher, and predicate logic didn't exist until after his death. Also, his work falls more under set theory than logic.Mathematical Logic became what it is (i.e., took off as popular) because of George Boole the mathematician.
The opposition to the "Square of Opposition" (which isn't actually in Aristotle) began over a millennia before Boole. Lucius Apuleius produced a different schematic in his treatise on logic written in the 2nd century (even if it was misattributed to him, the work is nonetheless that old). It was re-worked and challenged by the scholastics and early modern philosophers/mathematicians.Boole's challenge to the traditional Square of Opposition was famous and other developments made Boole an elite source for MATHEMATICAL LOGIC.
Actually, modern algebra allowed us to realized that Boole's work primarily on set theory (which is why even today Boolean logic/algebra uses set-theoretic notation) could be considered in terms of an algebra, but modern algebra (abstract algebra) wasn't yet sufficiently well developed to make the connections between logic, set theory, and algebra. Also, the binary nature of truth-bearing propositions means any formulation of classical (Aristotelian) logic is an algebra.His first formal writings were labled Algebraic logic.
That's not clarity, just inaccuracy:To be clear MATHEMATICAL LOGIC came about from developments AFTER BOOLE.
Wrong. It first appears in Mines' (1853) Presbyterian Clergyman, years before De Morgan's use. Also, the term "mathematical induction" goes back at least two decades before Mines' 1853 use of "mathematical logic". The term "mathematical philosophy" is attested to even earlier.Historically, DeMorgan was the first person to likely USE the term MATHEMATICAL LOGIC
You mean this? Ivor Grattan-Guinness states in his contribution to the volume on Peirce that the phrase “mathematical logic” was introduced by De Morgan in 1858 but that it served to distinguish logic using mathematics from “philosophical logic,” which was also a term used by De Morgan"My source for this is The Development of Modern Logic
No, it isn't. I own it. It's specific to modern logic, compared to e.g., the numerous volumes in the set Handbook to the History of Logic among many others and isn't actually as comprehensive as many a monograph or volume on the history of linguistics when it comes to the mathematization of logic. See e.g.,This source is BIG into the history of logic.
You need to read your source again.Mathematical logic on the other hand creates arguments just for the sake of writing symbols
Because my example illustrates how sorites' arguments are all examples of the paradox even if they don't appear paradoxical. In other words, the logical chain of sorites arguments paradoxically allows the proof of invalid conclusions using only valid premises and logical inference. That's the whole point: the nature of sorites arguments generally, not a particular paradox using the template. It's the fact that this polysyllogistic-type argument structure is not truth-preserving that is the paradox.You did not address what I asked but gave YOUR example.
No you wouldn't:I would have to quote half the book.
Then you shouldn't have made claims about "cathologic logic" and ignored e.g., Lewis Carroll's Symbolic Logic, the PM, Frege's two great works, or other work contemporary to or written prior to the works you cited, which are merely obscure and not representative of the ways in which anybody was educated (and weren't all logic texts).My purpose was to show that people WERE EDUCATED that way.
The writings were DIFFERENT time PERIODS
The Catholic priests that taught logic at Thomas Moore and CUA both used texts from Springer's UTM series (my brother's was actually Naïve Set Theory, not even mathematical logic). There is no "Catholic logic" and hasn't been since almost the beginnings of the reformation. When I lectured (and tutored) at the Jesuit university BC the texts used mathematical logic texts and modern philosophy of logic texts as well as e.g., The Logic of Theism (filled with not only mathematical logic but non-Aristotelian logics).My intention was to suggest that Catholic texts from any period will match the obsure texts terminology I used.
The point was to show how much propositional logic can't even represent. I suppose the inability for propositional logic to deal with quantifiers would have more clearly demonstrated how little of Aristotle propositional logic can deal with.Your notion of argument is certainly not TWO PREMISES with a CONCLUSION.