It was Cicero who, in De Legibus, first called Herodotus pater historiae but in the same breath he declared that in Herodotus sunt innumerabiles fabulae (1.5) Others have been less generous still, referring to him as the father of lies.
Herodotus liberties with the truth were well known even in ancient times. Ciceros comment on Herodotus fabulae has already been mentioned. The Latin fabulae corresponds quite well with the Greek mythos (Bettini 200), and thus Ciceros remark may be accurately taken as derogatory Ciceros passing slight is nothing when compared to Plutarchs malicious essay De Herodoti Malignitate. Plutarch maligns Herodotus and his work on multiple grounds, from his treatment of Thebes, Corinth, and the Boethians, to his deliberate malice: ou gar monon tes eschates adikias me onta dokein einai kiaion; alla kai kakoetheias akras ergon eukollian mimoumenon kai haploteat dusphoraton einai (1). He ends with a warning to potential readers: all osper en rodios dei kanthardia phylatesthai ten blasphemian autou kai kakologian, leiois kai hapalois schemasin hupodedikuian, hina me lathomen atopous kai pseudeis peri ton ariston kai megiston es Ellados poleon kai andron doxas labontes (43). However, it was Herodotus method against which Plutarch had the greatest problem: But what roused Plutarch's animus against Herodotus was his view of what history was all about. For Plutarch, history had a serious educational purpose (Evans 14). Apparently, Herodotus love of deeds and stories did not conform to Plutarchs understanding of what history ought to be. Other ancient authors wrote similar polemics of which we have fragments, including Against Herodotus by Manetho, On Herodotus' thefts, by Valerius Pollio, On Herodotus' lies, by Aelius Harpocration, and Against Herodotus by Libanius (Evans 14).
Thucydides too appears to have issues with the historical method employed by Herodotus. Although he does not actually name Herodotus, he does contrast his style with that employed by Herodotus: kai es men akroasin isos to me mythodes auton aterpesteron phaneitai; hosoi de boulesontai ton te genomenon to saphes skopein kai ton mellonton pote authis kata to anthropeion toiouton kai paraplesion esesthai, ophelima krinein auta arkountos hexei, ktema tee s aei mallon e agonisma es to paraxrema akouein xugkeitai (1.22.4). It appears that he is comparing himself to Herodotus, whose work is centered around to mythodes. Modern historians, particularly those of the 19th century when the idea of Herodotus as a father of lies was in scholarly vogue (Flory 64), have also rightly pointed out numerous liberties Herodotus took with the truth. Possible examples are numerous. Geography is of particular embarrassment for scholars wishing to defend the reputation of Herodotus, as it is the least of what a well-traveled historian could factually report: One reason for the embarrassment is that Herodotus' figures are badly wrong in the case of the Black Sea, where Herodotus' error on the length and breadth is one hundred percent and forty percent respectively, while his error on the more familiar Hellespont drops to one in six for both length and breadth, and that on the width of the Propontis to only one in seven (Armayor 47). Again:
Much more embarrassing is the great Scythian bronze of king Ariantas that Herodotus claims to have seen for himself. In view of his claim, we can only try to decipher what he saw in the light of metrology. According to standard metrology, that of Hultsch for example, Herodotus' amphoreus is a liquid measure equal to the Attic metretes and I.5 Roman amphorae or about 39.4 liters, or some 10.4 gallons. According to standard metrology, therefore, king Ariantas' 6oo-amphoreis bronze must have held upwards of 6,244 gallons, like Croesus' 6oo-amphoreis silver bowl at Delphi (i.5i). Herodotus does not mention Croesus' dedication in this passage. Jacoby argues that Herodotus must have gone to Scythia before he went to Delphi or else he would have, but in that case we are merely left to wonder why he did not mention the Scythian vessel when he came to tell about that of Delphi. But it seems difficult to believe a 6,244-gallon vessel in either place. (Armayor 51).
Herodotus various inaccurate or even mythic descriptions of geography present problems to any who would paint him as a dispassionate recorder of facts:
In the majority of these cases Herodotus casts a skeptical eye on the archaic legacy, leading some scholars to label him a 'Father of Empiricism,' but this formulation fails to account for other passages in which mythic and speculative thinking still predominate; indeed, the contradictions between the two approaches have led Lionel Pearson and others to question whether any coherent scheme of thought underlies Herodotean geography at all (Romm 98-99)
Geography is not the only place where Herodotus displays an affinity for the mythic over the factual and a certain carelessness with the truth. Of Herodotus account of Perdiccas, Kleinknecht writes, Der historische Wert der herodoteischen Überlieferung war damit erschöpft. Die Gründungssage selbst ist geschichtlich wertlos (136). Flory, in his chapter on Truth and Fiction in Herodotus points out that the first account given in the Histories of the strife between the Greeks and Persians is rationalism, pushed to its absurd extreme. Herodotus here parodies not just myth but rationalism itself. He makes the very plausibility of the demythologized tales suspect, particularly through unspoken or barely hinted comparison with the poetic originals He joins together totally different and timeless myths in a logical and orderly chronological sequence of cause and effect never suggested by the originals (25). Whether Florys designation of Herodotus style as containing playfully exaggerated seriousness (28) can be accepted is certainly debatable. What is not is Herodotus manipulation of myth into something designed to appear rational. It is no wonder Grant puzzles over the contrast between Herodotus the keen, shrewd, painstaking researcher and critic, and Herodotus careless and casual to the point of blamable negligence (283).
If Herodotus is thought of as the first historian, then certainly there are numerous issues to be found not only with his work but with his historical method. Herodotus does not ever state at the beginning of his book or anywhere else that he will tell only the truth about the past, for the father of history does not always accept the superiority of truth to fiction. Herodotus often tells lengthy stories he admits are false, disproves plausible stories, or accepts preposterous ones without proof (Flory 50).
Herodotus was certainly not the greatest of ancient historians, but he wasnt the worst either, and he certainly wasnt alone in reporting rumor, myth, magic, etc. Even better example may be found by examining not simply ancient history, but the genre of lives in which the gospels (more or less) fall. For example, Diogenes Laertius writes the lives of philosophers who lived centuries earlier, and his lives also contain wonder workings and miracles (for example, his descriptions of Pythagoras). Philostratus, in his Life of Apollonius not only discusses the various magic and wonders which Apollonius works, he is also removed from the events by over a century. Compared to biographies such as these, the gospels are far more likely to contain historical information mixed in with the mythical.
What is most important to note is that as a type of ancient biography, the gospels are concerned with history. This is not to say they view history in the same way that we do, or that they are unbiased observer of the events they describe, but that they were attempting to record accurately what they believed was the life of Jesus. This is important because scholars early in this century (particularly Bultmann) and prior (and even some today) argued that the gospels' authors, and the early Christians in general, showed no concern for the actual life of Jesus. Bultmann, for example, argued that early Christian communities freely attributed sayings to Jesus left and right, and so that very little in the gospels could be considered to trace back to Jesus. As we will see, not only did Bultmanns work predate several important and dominating studies on comparisons between the gospels and Greco-roman biography, he was also using a model of oral tradition that was woefully inaccurate (more on this later).
Of course, to say that the gospel authors were concerned with accurately recording a history/biography of Jesus and his teachings doesnt mean that the gospels themselves are accurate at all. I have already pointed out that several other biographers of the ancient world wrote biographies of people in which little to nothing may be accepted as true. All we can achieve by placing the gospels into a particular genre of ancient history is that 1) They arent myth, 2) The authors were recording history as they believed it.
Herodotus liberties with the truth were well known even in ancient times. Ciceros comment on Herodotus fabulae has already been mentioned. The Latin fabulae corresponds quite well with the Greek mythos (Bettini 200), and thus Ciceros remark may be accurately taken as derogatory Ciceros passing slight is nothing when compared to Plutarchs malicious essay De Herodoti Malignitate. Plutarch maligns Herodotus and his work on multiple grounds, from his treatment of Thebes, Corinth, and the Boethians, to his deliberate malice: ou gar monon tes eschates adikias me onta dokein einai kiaion; alla kai kakoetheias akras ergon eukollian mimoumenon kai haploteat dusphoraton einai (1). He ends with a warning to potential readers: all osper en rodios dei kanthardia phylatesthai ten blasphemian autou kai kakologian, leiois kai hapalois schemasin hupodedikuian, hina me lathomen atopous kai pseudeis peri ton ariston kai megiston es Ellados poleon kai andron doxas labontes (43). However, it was Herodotus method against which Plutarch had the greatest problem: But what roused Plutarch's animus against Herodotus was his view of what history was all about. For Plutarch, history had a serious educational purpose (Evans 14). Apparently, Herodotus love of deeds and stories did not conform to Plutarchs understanding of what history ought to be. Other ancient authors wrote similar polemics of which we have fragments, including Against Herodotus by Manetho, On Herodotus' thefts, by Valerius Pollio, On Herodotus' lies, by Aelius Harpocration, and Against Herodotus by Libanius (Evans 14).
Thucydides too appears to have issues with the historical method employed by Herodotus. Although he does not actually name Herodotus, he does contrast his style with that employed by Herodotus: kai es men akroasin isos to me mythodes auton aterpesteron phaneitai; hosoi de boulesontai ton te genomenon to saphes skopein kai ton mellonton pote authis kata to anthropeion toiouton kai paraplesion esesthai, ophelima krinein auta arkountos hexei, ktema tee s aei mallon e agonisma es to paraxrema akouein xugkeitai (1.22.4). It appears that he is comparing himself to Herodotus, whose work is centered around to mythodes. Modern historians, particularly those of the 19th century when the idea of Herodotus as a father of lies was in scholarly vogue (Flory 64), have also rightly pointed out numerous liberties Herodotus took with the truth. Possible examples are numerous. Geography is of particular embarrassment for scholars wishing to defend the reputation of Herodotus, as it is the least of what a well-traveled historian could factually report: One reason for the embarrassment is that Herodotus' figures are badly wrong in the case of the Black Sea, where Herodotus' error on the length and breadth is one hundred percent and forty percent respectively, while his error on the more familiar Hellespont drops to one in six for both length and breadth, and that on the width of the Propontis to only one in seven (Armayor 47). Again:
Much more embarrassing is the great Scythian bronze of king Ariantas that Herodotus claims to have seen for himself. In view of his claim, we can only try to decipher what he saw in the light of metrology. According to standard metrology, that of Hultsch for example, Herodotus' amphoreus is a liquid measure equal to the Attic metretes and I.5 Roman amphorae or about 39.4 liters, or some 10.4 gallons. According to standard metrology, therefore, king Ariantas' 6oo-amphoreis bronze must have held upwards of 6,244 gallons, like Croesus' 6oo-amphoreis silver bowl at Delphi (i.5i). Herodotus does not mention Croesus' dedication in this passage. Jacoby argues that Herodotus must have gone to Scythia before he went to Delphi or else he would have, but in that case we are merely left to wonder why he did not mention the Scythian vessel when he came to tell about that of Delphi. But it seems difficult to believe a 6,244-gallon vessel in either place. (Armayor 51).
Herodotus various inaccurate or even mythic descriptions of geography present problems to any who would paint him as a dispassionate recorder of facts:
In the majority of these cases Herodotus casts a skeptical eye on the archaic legacy, leading some scholars to label him a 'Father of Empiricism,' but this formulation fails to account for other passages in which mythic and speculative thinking still predominate; indeed, the contradictions between the two approaches have led Lionel Pearson and others to question whether any coherent scheme of thought underlies Herodotean geography at all (Romm 98-99)
Geography is not the only place where Herodotus displays an affinity for the mythic over the factual and a certain carelessness with the truth. Of Herodotus account of Perdiccas, Kleinknecht writes, Der historische Wert der herodoteischen Überlieferung war damit erschöpft. Die Gründungssage selbst ist geschichtlich wertlos (136). Flory, in his chapter on Truth and Fiction in Herodotus points out that the first account given in the Histories of the strife between the Greeks and Persians is rationalism, pushed to its absurd extreme. Herodotus here parodies not just myth but rationalism itself. He makes the very plausibility of the demythologized tales suspect, particularly through unspoken or barely hinted comparison with the poetic originals He joins together totally different and timeless myths in a logical and orderly chronological sequence of cause and effect never suggested by the originals (25). Whether Florys designation of Herodotus style as containing playfully exaggerated seriousness (28) can be accepted is certainly debatable. What is not is Herodotus manipulation of myth into something designed to appear rational. It is no wonder Grant puzzles over the contrast between Herodotus the keen, shrewd, painstaking researcher and critic, and Herodotus careless and casual to the point of blamable negligence (283).
If Herodotus is thought of as the first historian, then certainly there are numerous issues to be found not only with his work but with his historical method. Herodotus does not ever state at the beginning of his book or anywhere else that he will tell only the truth about the past, for the father of history does not always accept the superiority of truth to fiction. Herodotus often tells lengthy stories he admits are false, disproves plausible stories, or accepts preposterous ones without proof (Flory 50).
Herodotus was certainly not the greatest of ancient historians, but he wasnt the worst either, and he certainly wasnt alone in reporting rumor, myth, magic, etc. Even better example may be found by examining not simply ancient history, but the genre of lives in which the gospels (more or less) fall. For example, Diogenes Laertius writes the lives of philosophers who lived centuries earlier, and his lives also contain wonder workings and miracles (for example, his descriptions of Pythagoras). Philostratus, in his Life of Apollonius not only discusses the various magic and wonders which Apollonius works, he is also removed from the events by over a century. Compared to biographies such as these, the gospels are far more likely to contain historical information mixed in with the mythical.
What is most important to note is that as a type of ancient biography, the gospels are concerned with history. This is not to say they view history in the same way that we do, or that they are unbiased observer of the events they describe, but that they were attempting to record accurately what they believed was the life of Jesus. This is important because scholars early in this century (particularly Bultmann) and prior (and even some today) argued that the gospels' authors, and the early Christians in general, showed no concern for the actual life of Jesus. Bultmann, for example, argued that early Christian communities freely attributed sayings to Jesus left and right, and so that very little in the gospels could be considered to trace back to Jesus. As we will see, not only did Bultmanns work predate several important and dominating studies on comparisons between the gospels and Greco-roman biography, he was also using a model of oral tradition that was woefully inaccurate (more on this later).
Of course, to say that the gospel authors were concerned with accurately recording a history/biography of Jesus and his teachings doesnt mean that the gospels themselves are accurate at all. I have already pointed out that several other biographers of the ancient world wrote biographies of people in which little to nothing may be accepted as true. All we can achieve by placing the gospels into a particular genre of ancient history is that 1) They arent myth, 2) The authors were recording history as they believed it.